Planning
is
the process by which he selects a course of action (a set of means) for the
attainment
of his ends. It is “good” planning if these means are likely to attain the
ends
or maximize the chances of their attainment. It is by the process of rational
choice
that the best adaptation of means to ends is likely to be achieved.
- Banfield, Edward C. Reprinted from the International Social
Science Journal Vol. XI No.3, 1959, with the permission of UNESCO. Retrieved
from http://www.pmf.unizg.hr/_download/repository/Banfield_Ends_and_Means_in_Planning.pdf.
Process of Preparing a
Rational Plan
a
rational decision is one made in the following manner:
(a)
the decision-maker lists all the opportunities for action open to him;
(b)
he identifies all the con sequences which would follow from the adoption of
each
of the possible actions; and
(c)
he selects the action which would he followed by
the
preferred set of consequences.
RATIONAL PLANNING
A
rational decision is one in which alternatives and consequences are considered
as fully as the decision-maker, given the time and other resources available to
him, can afford to consider them.
A
plan (unless we depart very far from customary usage) is a decision with regard
to a
course
of action. A course of action is a sequence of acts which are mutually related
as
means and are therefore viewed as a unit; it is the unit which is the plan.
Planning,
then,
as defined here, is to be distinguished from what we may call “opportunistic
decision-making”,
which is choosing (rationally or not) actions that are not mutually
related
as a single means. The rational selection of a course of action, i.e. the
making
of a rational plan, involves
essentially the same procedure as any rational choice:
every possible course of action must be
listed, all the consequences which would
follow from each course must he
identified, and that course selected the consequences
of
which are preferred.
The
process by which a plan is rationally made may conveniently he described under
four
main headings:
1.
Analysis of the situation. The planner must lay down in prospect
every possible
course
of action which would lead to the attainment of the ends sought. His task is to
imagine
how the actor may get from where he is to where he wants to be, but his
imagination
must work within certain conditions which are fixed by the situation,
especially
by the resources at his disposal (not merely possessions, of course, but legal
and
other authority, information, time, executive skill, and so on) and by the
obstacles
in
his way. His opportunity area consists of the courses of action “really” open
to him,
i.e.
those which he is not precluded from taking by some limiting condition. It may
be,
of
course, that he has no opportunity area at all - that there is absolutely no
way by
which
the ends sought may be achieved - or that the opportunity area is a very
restricted
one.
2.
End reduction and elaboration. An end is an image of a future state
of affairs
towards
which action is oriented. The formulation of the end may be extremely vague
and
diffuse. If so it may have to be reduced to specific or “operational” terms
before it
can
serve as a criterion of choice in the concrete circumstances. The formulation
of
the
end may be elliptical; in this case the planner must clearly explain the
meaning in
full.
An end may be thought of as having both active and contextual elements. The
active
elements are those features of the future situation which are actively sought;
the
contextual
are those which, while not actively sought, nevertheless cannot be
sacrificed
without loss. (The man who burned down his house in order to get the rats
out
of the cellar ignored a contextual end in his effort to achieve an active one.)
The
planner’s
task is to identify and clarify the contextual as well as the active
components
of the ends. If they are not fully consistent, he must also “order” them,
i.e.
he must discover the relative value to be attached to each under the various
concrete
circum stances envisaged in the courses of action or, as an economist would
say,
prepare an “indifference map”.
3.
The design of courses of action.
Courses of action may have a more or a
less
general
character. At the most general level, a developing course of action implies a
description
of the “key” actions to be taken or the commitments to be made. These
constitute
the premises upon which any less general course of action is based, e.g. at
the
“programme” or “operations” levels. In other words, decisions of a less general
character
represent choices from among those alternatives which are not precluded by
the
more general decisions already taken. A developing course of action may be
chosen
arbitrarily or capriciously and a programmed course of action based upon it
may
then be selected with elaborate consideration of alternatives and consequences:
in
such
a case there is “functional rationality” but “substantive irrationality”.
4.
The comparative evaluation of consequences. If the plan is to be rational, all
consequences—not
merely those intended by the planner—must be taken into
account.
To a large extent, then, good planning is a search for unintended
consequences
which might follow from the attainment of the active or contextual
ends.
The planner cannot pick and choose among the consequences of a given course
of
action: he must take them all, the unwanted along with the wanted, as a set.
Their
evaluation
therefore must be in terms of the net value attached to each set. If all values
could
be expressed in terms of a common numerical index (e.g. prices) this would
raise
no great difficulties. In practice, however, the planner must somehow strike a
balance
between essentially unlike intangibles. He must decide, for example, whether
X
amount of damage to a beautiful view is justified by Y amount of increase in
driving
safety.
Despite
this lack, some general observations are possible. While the Chicago Housing
Authority may be a rather extreme case, there are compelling reasons which
militate against planning and rationality on the part of all organizations.
1.
Organizations do not lay out courses of action, because the future is highly
uncertain.
There are very few matters about which reliable predictions can be made
for
more than five years ahead.
2.
When it is possible to decide upon a course of action well in advance it is
likely to
be
imprudent to do so, or at least to do so publicly (as, of course, a public
agency
ordinarily
must). For to advertise in advance the actions that are to be taken is to
invite
opposition to them and to give the opposition a great advantage. This is a
principle
which many city planners have learned to their cost.
3.
Organizations, especially public ones, do not consider fundamental alternatives
because
usually there are circumstances which preclude them, at least in the short run,
from
doing anything very different from what they are already doing. Some of these
circumstances
may be the result of choices which the organization has already made;
others
may be externally imposed.
4.
Organizations have a decided preference for present rather than future effects.
One
might
think that public organizations, at least, would be more willing than are
persons
to
postpone satisfactions—that, in the language of economics, they would discount
the
future
less heavily. They do not seem to, however, and this is another reason why they
do not
plan ahead.
5.
The reason they discount the future so heavily is, perhaps, that they must
continually
be preoccupied with the present necessity of maintaining what Barnard
has
called the “economy of incentives”.
6.
The end of organizational maintenance—of keeping the organization going for the
sake
of keeping it going—is usually more important than any substantive end.
7.
The end-system of an organization is rarely, if ever, a clear and coherent
picture of
a
desirable future toward which action is to be directed.
8.
It follows that serious reflection on the ends of the organization, and
especially any
attempt
to state ends in precise and realistic terms, is likely to be destructive to
the
organization.
9.
It follows also that organizations do not as a rule attempt to maximize the
attainment
of their ends or (to say the same thing in different words) to use resources
efficiently.
10.
Laying out courses of action, clarifying ends, and evaluating alternatives are
costly
procedures which take time and money and cannot he carried out without the
active
participation of the chief executives.
11.
Rationality, as defined above, is less likely to he found in public than in
private
organizations.
One reason for this is that the public agency’s ends often reflect
compromise
among essentially incompatible interests.
12.
Whether or not conflict is built into the end-system, the end-systems of public
organizations
are vastly more complex than those of private ones.
- Banfield, Edward C. Reprinted from the International Social
Science Journal Vol. XI No.3, 1959, with the permission of UNESCO. Retrieved
from http://www.pmf.unizg.hr/_download/repository/Banfield_Ends_and_Means_in_Planning.pdf.
Integrative Approaches to
Planning
In recent years, planning
practice has been characterized by its heterodox nature of many different
specializations and disciplines working in separation of one another on
different scales. With so many disciplines and diverse experiences, cities
still suffer from many chronic urban problems. Because of theinadequacy in
planning practice and processes, many urban problems related to social justice,
spatial segregation based on socioeconomic classification of the population,
inequitable distribution of resources and services, unemployment, traffic
congestion, urban sprawl and fragmentation, environmental pollution and
degradation, resources depletion, and unsustainable nature of urban form have
occurred (Visser, 2001). With the lack of an overarching multi-scalar planning
framework, many of these severe problems will continue to occur, grow, and
fester. Based on this realization, in the past half century there has been a
recent push in the planning community towards formulating more integrated approaches
to planning to deal with complex urban realities. Recognizing the proliferation
of the aforementioned urban problems, two key reasons are identified to support
the formulation of a new integrated planning practice. First, planning practice
is heterogeneous. There are many
competing, evolving, and complementary sets of ideas and subjects that are
scattered across a continuum of different specializations. This evident
isolation and segregation of different and separate planning disciplines seems
to hinder planning practitioners to confront the notoriously complex urban
realities and interrelated and messy urban problems. The challenge that these
problems pose is not confined to the fact that they are messy and complex, but
it also stems from their cross-disciplinary nature. This means that a single
problem, although it has its roots in a single field, context, or scale, can extend
to affect many other areas, planning aspects, and scales. This
trans-disciplinary nature of city and metropolitan problems calls for an
interdisciplinary bridging in planning practice, without which practitioners
will grow unable to engender consensus over important planning decisions, what
to do, and most importantly, what not to do. Second, plans and projects are
conducted in many planning fields and sectors for different purposes, at different
times and on different scales, which produces high levels of dysfunctionality
and institutional and decision-making fragmentation (Pieterse, 2002). Because
these projects are usually bound to the scale and magnitude they are attempting
to approach, seldom do they account for each other. However, urban problems do
not have boundaries to their impacts or effects which permeate across all
scales varying from local to regional, and even national, or in some known cases
global. In fact, these urban problems perpetually extend across space and time.
Planning issues that seem to have local impacts can also have more serious and
detrimental regional and national impacts when considered in aggregate. This
suggests the importance of across-space and time planning approaches that
account for short and long-term consequences and multiple levels of impacts of
city and metropolitan scale problems including local, regional, and national
levels.
To that end, there is an
increasingly perceived need for a multidisciplinary integrated planning
approach to provide better tools to guide actions towards the development of
healthy cities, improvement of human conditions, and ultimately a better
urbanism. By thoughtfully employing elements of integrative planning in the
decision-making process, decision makers can focus their attention on
identifying the real current and foreseeable future needs of the community and
channel their efforts towards satisfying these needs through the physical
development of the city and the reordering and rectification of urban space.
The divergence, segmentation,
and segregation of planning efforts of different agencies that may result in
duplication of analyses and waste of time and resources are prime driving
forces for streamlining these efforts. Many sectors of planning, which tend to
have their own goals, visions, policies, and strategies, need to be combined
together and linked to one another. Under
different names, such as
comprehensive, regional, or master plans, comprehensive planning originally
emerged to meet this particular need.
Proponents of comprehensive
planning perceive it as necessary rational tool that incorporates multiple
essential elements of planning including physical land use planning and social,
economic, and environmental aspects to safeguard public interest and guide the
city’s long-range future (Friedmann, 1971). Conversely, accusations of
comprehensive planning failure made by its opponents rely on a number of reasons
in support of their argument. Opponents of
integrative comprehensive
planning approaches ground their argument on the practical difficulties in
coping with multilayered problems and cooperating with multiple policy domains
that makes crafting adequate plans prohibitively insurmountable. These
difficulties stem from the limitation of individual planners and institutional
settings that seem to be overwhelmed by numerous practical complications. As
such, integrative comprehensive planning is often accused of offering an
impractical and overly ambitious approach. It reflects unrealistically ideal
assumptions of human capacity and socioeconomic, structural, and organizational
settings. The rational-comprehensive approach neglects quintessential
characteristics of real-world decision-making situations, namely the
fallibility of human comprehension ability, the limitation in resources, time,
and access to information, the multiplicity of competing rational actors and
power structure imbalance (Forester, 1989). The assumption of comprehensive
intellectual
human abilities is an
invidiously problematic one. Humans cannot comprehend everything nor can they
even fully comprehend one planning aspect (Lindblom, 1959). They tend to rely
on simplification of intricate issues to reach satisfactory decisions rather
than optimal solutions, based on which process important possible outcomes,
alternative potential policies, and affected values are often neglected or
overlooked (Lindblom, 1959). As such, planning comprehensively seems beyond
human cognitive ability and institutional, technical and organizational
capacity (Lindblom, 1959).
Both truth and rationality
are context-dependent and mean different things to different people. Although
it exists in separation from our seemingly neatly compartmentalized and deeply
conflicted belief, universal rationality is received, filtered, interpreted,
manipulated and constructed differently, reflecting the diversity of frame of
reference of each individual. Because of its constructed nature, universal
rationality cannot be realized as, or in, a single form. This divergence in
views of rationality is greatly influenced by personal values, experiences, and
power relations (Camillus, 1982). There is a struggle between power and reason
which results in the prevalence of power over rationality whenever they clash
in practice. Rationality alone seems insufficient to assuage power. With the
presence of power, the role of rationality is usually underestimated and
diminished or, worse yet, utilized to serve hegemonic interests. In fact,
universal rationality has long been used by technocratic elites to solidify
superiority over others as a way of manipulation, intimidation and exclusion.
In this regard, decisions are not made based on facts, but rather facts are
often made based on predetermined decisions. This does not mean that planners
cannot act rationally or rely on a certain degree of common rationality and
reason. This is because acting rationally and sensibly is different than
relying on universal rationality. Conflict occurrence does not necessarily
indicate our inability to reach consensus, and the absence of universal rules
that can be applied in every situation does not necessarily lead to a lack of
consensus on common foundations of rationality and reason. However, this common
rationality and reason, which can only go as far as common sense, is not
elaborate enough to act in separation of contextual details of planning
practice in different jurisdictions. As such, rationality beyond common sense
is hard to gain wide acceptance and therefore its generalizability and
universality is simply beyond the realm of possibility.
This context-laden nature of
planning problems and solutions suggests that truth or rationality depends
primarily on the context within which these problems were generated. Ignoring
the importance of context by relying on allegations of monolithic planning
rationality allows no room for public participation and only hinders the
planners’ ability to innovate new ideas. This suggests the reliance on
alternative narratives that are cognizant of contextual differences and
attentively cautious in
interpreting certain narratives, claims of truth and universal rationality.
Contextualization of planning
problems suggests orchestration and facilitation of efforts and participation
in order to generate much needed debates about the appropriateness of
solutions, and nature and scale of response. Debate does not necessarily mean
undermining other points of view or that quarreling would ensue. Through debate
and consensus building, brilliant ideas can surface and only the most effective
argument can prevail. Further, best alternatives can be evaluated, arguments
can be sharpened, and good ideas can also be improved by discussion and feedback
from each other. Questioning who wins and who loses based on what decisions and
by what mechanisms helps deconstruct and debunk allegations of spoken and
unspoken universal truth that often produces such mechanisms and patterns.
Without this counter-hegemonic discourse whose goal is to unmask taken
for-granted truths, hidden constructedness will remain ever hidden and
legitimized by political and bureaucratic constituents for the purpose of only
self-aggrandizement (Robbins, 2004).
The
Role of Power and Politics in Plan-making and Plan Implementation
Power and politics have a
significant role in plan-making and implementation. Planning inherently relies
on means of communicative and interactive discourse, through which hegemonic
power habitually permeates. The misconception of planning as a merely
scientific and technical endeavor resulted in planners’ inability to deal with,
and confront, the many types of power. Due to this evident political
illiteracy, many planners fail to gain political interest and in turn their
plans appear to lack, in many cases, proper implementation. The lack of
engagement in political processes and the failure to manage successful plan
implementation represents poor practice and a misconception of planners as
technically-astute individuals whose field of influence is confined to their
workstation located in their cubical. This technocratic confinement of planning
and planners created a gap between what’s being done, which is merely
influenced by political forces; and what people want to see happen in their
communities in the future, which planners often claim to capture and engender
in their plans.
Making influential decisions
means making action-oriented decisions, on one hand, and being able to
successfully implement them, on the other. This however cannot be attained
without realizing and utilizing both soft and hard power as a means to arrive
to this end of being influential. By relying onelements of soft power,
including discussion, negotiation, mediation, diplomacy, and even argument,
people can reach agreements and common ground on some of the most formidable
and severely disputed issues. In contradistinction, hard power personifies
operation-oriented actions and plans, implementation and enforcement
mechanisms, political clout, economic incentives, collective social actions and
even revolutions, and any other necessary means to change undesirable conditions.
Hence, planning should depart from the idealized notion of neutrality or the
notion of being inherently consensus-based. The challenge remains for planners
to be able to develop expertise and skills not only to anticipate and respond
to future power influence and agenda setting, but also to counteract its
implications on
democratic planning practice.
This calls for the realization that neither the utter dominance of the power
approach nor the complete elimination or negligence of the existence of the
power approach work in practice. The need to be in touch with reality
(Flyvbjerg, 2001), with its wicked face and the existence of power dynamics and
relations, calls for the insightful understanding of power structure by
acknowledging its existence and impacts, on one hand, and the innovation and
employment of creative integrative planning tools that utilize power to delimit,
counteract, and neutralize power, on the other hand. This requires proactive
involvement in the political and social arenas of decision-making. Wielding
power for planners, on one hand, means being able to make decisions that have
the potential to change reality; and to wield power, on the other hand,
planners should become an active part of the “game” not just the audience, or
worse yet, cheerleaders.
An Agenda
for an Alternative Path to an Integrative Approach to Planning
Proposition (1): with this in
mind, a mature adaptive application of planning theory should incorporate an
examination of the development of cities in the past, the relationship between
political and economic forces and cultural and social structures, and
understanding of how power relationships shape political realities and
decision-making. While discourse can provide part of the explanation, a further
step is to engender a deep understanding of the structures of power that not only
guide discourse but in many cases generate it.
Proposition (2): an
effective planning theory should consider the adaptive sustainable planning
model as an overarching normative framework and ideal of a useful integrative
approach to planning problems. Under the auspices of the notion of adaptive sustainability,
this model encompasses two key components (sustainable planning amalgamated to
adaptive learning and consensus building), which makes it exceptionally
functional and enhances its applicability. While sustainable planning provides
process guidance, or “rules of engagement,” adaptive learning and application
provides institutional resilience and governance, or “mechanisms
of engagement.” This approach encompasses adequate procedural aspects, the
institutional ability to create political alliances, and the power to influence
outcomes with the flexibility to accommodate different social and spatial
contexts, and the aspiration to promote legitimate public input in pursuance of
the common good. Given its holistic merits, integrative adaptive sustainable
planning is equally concerned with short and long-term consequences. Employing
available resources and
seeking to obtain new resources to satiate community’s needs (Visser, 2001),
this approach effectively aims to assess current and future community’s needs,
limitations, and opportunities and establish frameworks for collaboratively
setting visions, goals, policies, and strategies to meet these needs in a
timely fashion (Camillus, 1982).
First: rules of engagement: every
decision made by planners and policy makers personifies a
profound challenge of how to
maintain a speedy growth pattern to keep up with cutting-edge
technological advancement,
population demand, and growth requirements, while at the same time safeguard
social justice (for current and future generations) and promote environmental
protection. These problems and challenges suggest the need to rely on new
strategies of planning and development.
As illustrated in figure 1,
the sustainability model conceptualizes planning as a triangle that personifies
a synergistic integration of three main competing interests including equity,
economy, and the environment, or what is known as the “3 Es”
(Campbell and Fainstein, 2003). Although planning is ideally intended to
enhance economic growth, preserve the environment, and foster social justice,
practically different planners, depending on their background, vision, and
value system, act differently, which leads to one of these outcomes or another.
This model suggests that sustainable planning can be attained through the
mindful balance of these three conflicting planning goals within the society.
Setting sustainability as a
desired target has three practical benefits for planning. The first practical
benefit is that sustainability can be used as a template against which to
objectively judge certain plans, based on the extent to which they adhere to
these sustainability concerns, and to confront and evaluate frequent claims and
allegations of sustainability. The second practical benefit is, once a number
of proposed plans, scenarios, or polices are identified to be sustainable based
on the first measure, this model provides a reference point based on which we
can assess them and select the most sustainable one based on its vicinity to
attaining sustainability, which resides at the center of the triangle. Despite
its incommensurable nature, sustainability is something that we can acquire
more of. The closer a certain plan is to the center, the more sustainable it is
deemed and therefore it is the more preferred one compared to other proposed
sustainable plans. Sustainability provides a path to a desirable and
appropriate outcome. It is
therefore a means to an end, not an end by itself. It helps us set goals, objectives,
and visions for the future. It also poses a reminder of what planning is most
concerned with; spearheading the quest of satiating the interests of all
groups, addressing and resolving conflicts, and promoting a better quality of
life for all. Third, using this model helps not only in understanding planning
and its priorities and successfully managing these common clashes of interest
(Campbell, 1996), but also in providing an adequate normative framework to
organize the practice and scholarship of planning, on one hand, and a stance
that orients us, on the other. This does not mean that following the
sustainability model will ensure elimination of these conflicts. On the
contrary, following this model will in fact trigger conflicts and generate
debate, which are real and healthy. They are real because they are inevitable and occur in
every planning decision; and healthy because they tend to produce
and carry on fruitful and meaningful debate among different actors and sectors
of planning that boosts acceptance and willingness to question and be
questioned, and in turn generate more robust and informed decisions.
Second: mechanisms of
engagement: the second element of the proposed integrative planning
emanates from, and responds
to, the critiques of sustainability as an integrative planning discourse and
its political and institutional challenges. Akin to other planning approaches,
sustainability seems to provide an ambitious approach that attempts to cover a
great deal of ground, which may impose difficulties in institutional settings,
governmental cooperation, and decision-making mechanisms. Such integrated
planning approaches are often challenged by political and institutional
realities, established planning and decision-making practices and bureaucratic
processes. Bureaucratic processes, which were once believed to stimulate and
integrate local decisions into larger schemes, appear to not only limit the
capacity and influence of these decisions, but may also resist such integrated
approaches (Wank, 1996). The complex decision-making process related to the
institutional configuration of each community, where organizations display
complex hierarchal relationships, makes it hard for any new integrative
planning approach to succeed. In particular, planning agencies operate under
different jurisdictions with different legal and institutional basis. This
divergence of different modes of government in various realms of social and
institutional life of communities constitutes a major challenge to the
integration of planning systems (Meadowcroft, 1997). However, this argument of
cooperation mishaps can be turned on its heels. The fact that we have
cooperation difficulties on both individual and institutional levels does not
suggest that finding a meaningful resolution is insurmountable. On the contrary,
these difficulties serve as the crisis/tragedy narrative that justifies
developing this integrative approach. It is imperative for this approach to
realize that real-life planning had, has, and will always have many obstacles
in the way of making and adopting plans, which suggests that the assumption of
a single approach capable of resolving all of these problems is unrealistic at
best.
Adaptive management
incorporates an assessment of the past and current planning status and a
formulation of a response to change the status quo. This requires the
development of general rules and guidelines for urban
affairs, free access of information acquisition and dissemination, and a
developmentally incremental social learning process that encompasses
technological, educational and information systems.
Relying on technical,
political and democratic participation processes, it integrates planning
processes with the institutional structure of local, state, and federal
governments to allow for more power and incorporate citizenry participation in
the process. As such, it, building on the bottom-up perspective, serves as a
device to facilitate communication across all levels of the government
structures to ensure that the development of the city as an urban settlement
is conducted in a way that
benefits a broader range of its inhabitants (Visser, 2001).
participatory planning to
allow for real cooperation, generate feedback mechanisms, and meet the need for
flexibility and adaptability. Through participatory planning, the sustainable
planning agenda can be shifted towards ongoing, evolving, and transformative
learning, where insights from a broad range of stakeholders and disciplines can
be garnered. By engaging in dialectic discourses, planners and their
communities can learn about not only their arguments and that of others, but
also about themselves as well as others and therefore can form and reform their
social and political interactions and relationships. Through consensus building
processes and inter-discursive communication that equally involve and inform
all affected and interested stakeholders without the dominance of one over the
other, all participants can freely speak, listen to each other, and question
the status
quo.
To chart the course to a desirable and acceptable future for their communities,
planners, working as facilitators, need to connect with their communities and
work closely with people on identifying and addressing issues that most concern
them.
Proposition (3): the
creation of viable directions for new integrative planning paradigms is
contingent upon the cultivation of locally engaged, yet regionally in tune
efforts; the redefining of an ever-changing and impermanent language of
planning difference; and the acknowledgment of global political and economic
realities as connected webs of local transformations. Under these conditions,
planning practice should be transformed from something transferable to
something that emanates from within “here and now.” While confining planning
efforts to the local level will only foster fragmentation, working together in
unity will build a planning community that perpetuates a larger scale effort
able to confront power on its own terrain (Gibson-Graham, 2006).
Proposition (4): the value
system, which appears to be highly diverse, poses a challenge of how such
greatly diverse interests and orientations can come to terms with a distinct
and conclusive definition of an integrative approach to planning practice that
not only captures the essence of such a sophisticated, diverse, and mature
field, but also satiates this heterogeneity in specializations, interests, and
educational and practical backgrounds. Regardless of what definition we may
produce, or how well the definition is able to precisely and comprehensively outline
the new approach to planning, seeking consensus on what this approach is will
always be a major challenge that calls for effective practical solutions.
Consequently, the real challenge, reflecting the struggle that planners face
everyday in their decisions, is to figure out ways for people to accept a
definition of this integrated approach, whatever may be, and live with it.
In a nutshell, undesired
consequences often happen not because of lack of planning, but because of
inadequacy in planning processes, decisions, policies, and outcome. This
inadequacy includes intentional or unintentional separation of planning from
the political process, planners’ unawareness of power structures, inconsistency
of decisions and segregation of planning specializations that tend to alienate
different planning practitioners from one another. Planners need a well-defined
frame of reference to what they do, and not do, based on which they can operate knowing
what they can do, when to do certain things and when to refrain form doing
others. Defining an alternative planning approach will provide planners with a
comprehensive lens through which they can see the world and therefore
insightfully interact with it. While integrative planning approaches are deemed
necessary and
desirable, the adaptive
sustainability model emerges as a compelling and useful model in providing
these important characteristics for the development of the field. Without such
adequate approaches, it would be hard for planners to mark solid and firm ground,
on which they can build, identify, and develop planning as a discipline and as
a profession.
1. What
are the types of rationality, their similarities and differences?
Practical Rationality
Weber designates every way of life that views and judges worldly activity in
relation to the individual's purely pragmatic and egoistic interests as
practical rational. Pragmatic action in terms of everyday interests is
ascendant, and given practical ends are attained by careful weighing and
increasingly precise calculation of the most adequate means ([1946] 1958f, p.
293 [266]). Thus, this type of rationality exists as a manifestation of man's
capacity for means-end rational action.
Theoretical Rationality
(intellectual rationality) This type of rationality involves a conscious
mastery of reality through the construction of increasingly precise abstract
concepts rather than through action. Since a cognitive confrontation with one's
experience pre- vails here, such thought processes as logical deduction and
induction, the attribution of causality, and the formation of symbolic
"meanings" are typical. More generally, all abstract cognitive
processes, in all their ex- pansive active forms, denote theoretical rationality.
Unlike the means-end
rational action that provides the foundation for purely adaptive practical
rationality, theoretical rationalization processes are undergirded and given
their momentum, Weber argues, by the natural "metaphysical need" and
"irrepressible quest" of thinkers and systematiz- ers to transcend sheer
given routine and to supply the random events of everyday life with a coherent
"meaning.
Substantive Rationality
Like practical rationality though unlike theoretical rationality, substantive
rationality directly orders action into patterns. It does so, however, not on
the basis of a purely means-end calculation of solutions to routine problems
but in relation to a past, present, or potential "value postulate"
(1968, pp. 85-86 [44-45]). Not simply a single value, such as positive
evaluation of wealth or of the fulfillment of duty, a value postulate im- plies
entire clusters of values that vary in comprehensiveness, internal consistency,
and content. Thus, this type of rationality exists as a mani- festation of
man's inherent capacity for value-rational action. A substantive rationality
may be circumscribed, organizing only a de- limited area of life and leaving
all others untouched. Friendship, for example, whenever it involves adherence
to such values as loyalty, com- passion, and mutual assistance, constitutes a
substantive rationality. Com- munism, feudalism, hedonism, egalitarianism,
Calvinism, socialism, Bud- dhism, Hinduism, and the Renaissance view of life,
no less than all aesthetic notions of "the beautiful," are also
examples of substantive rationalities, however far they may diverge in their
capacity to organize action as well as in their value content (1968, pp. 44-45
[85]).
. Instead, a radical
perspectivism prevails in which the exis- tence of a rationalization process
depends on an individual's implied or stated, unconscious or conscious,
preference for certain ultimate values and the systematization of his or her
action to conform to these values. These values acquire "rationality"
merely from their status as consistent value postulates. Similarly, the
"irrational" is not fixed and intrinsically "irrational"
but results from the ideal-typical incompatibility of one ulti- mate
constellation of values with another: Something is not of itself
"irrational," but rather becomes so when ex- amined from a specific
"rational" standpoint. Every religious person is
"irrational" for every irreligious person, and every hedonist
likewise views every ascetic way of life as "irrational," even if,
measured in terms of its ultimate values, a "rationalization" has
taken place. This essay, if it can make any contribution at all, aims to expose
the multifaceted nature of a concept-the "rational"-that only appears
to be a simple one. [(1930) 1958a, p. 53, n. 9 (35, n. 1); my translation,
emphasis in original]12
Formal Rationality Unlike
the intercivilizational and epoch-transcending character of the prac- tical,
theoretical, and substantive types of rationality, formal rationality
generally14 relates to spheres of life and a structure of domination that
acquired specific and delineated boundaries only with industrialization: most
significantly, the economic, legal, and scientific spheres, and the
bureaucratic form of domination. Whereas practical rationality always indicates
a diffuse tendency to calculate and to solve routine problems by means-end
rational patterns of action in reference to pragmatic self- interests, formal
rationality ultimately legitimates a similar means-end rational calculation by
reference back to universally applied rules, laws, or regulation.
Practical and formal types
of rationality are based typically on man's capacity for means-end rational
action; substantive rationality derives typically from value-rational action.
Even though theoretical rationality, on the other hand, is rooted in abstract
cognitive processes instead of action, rational action-and even patterns of
rational action-may follow indirectly from theoretical rational thinking.
Substantive, formal, and
theoretical types of rationality do not, in We- ber's scheme, remain simply amorphous
sociocultural regularities of action. Instead, given configurations of
facilitating sociological and historical fac- tors, they are institutionalized
as normative regularities of action with-in "legitimate orders" :17
organizations,18 traditional (patriarchal, patri- monial, feudal) and
rational-legal (bureaucratic) forms of domination, types of economic
structures, ethical doctrines, classes, and strata. The diffuse,
problem-solving character of practical rationality generally con- fines it to the
domain of routine, everyday, pragmatic difficulties.
CONSCIOUS MASTERY OF FRAGMENTED REALITIES
THROUGH REGULARITIES OF ACTION
Type
of Rationality
|
Mental
Processes
|
Relation
to Action
|
Mental
Processes
|
Theoretical
|
Various
abstract processes
|
Indirect
|
Values
or purely theoretical problems
|
Practical
|
Means-end
calculation
|
Direct
|
Interests
|
Formal
|
Means-end
calculation
|
Direct
|
Rules,
laws, regulations
|
Substantive
|
Subordination
of realities
|
Direct
|
Values
to values
|
Weber defines an
"ethical" standard as ". . . a specific type of value- rational
belief among individuals which, as a consequence of this belief, imposes a
normative element upon human action that claims the quality of the 'morally
good' in the same way that action which claims the status of the 'beautiful' is
measured against aesthetic standards" (1968, p. 36 [19]; translation
altered, emphasis in original)
Ethical rationality does
not involve simply the memorization of rules for proper conduct that putatively
contain the cumulative wisdom of past generations. Instead, ethical action
implies, first, an imperative for cQn- formity to a moral good that is felt to
be internally binding or obligatory
In sum, substantive
rationality is the only type of rationality that possesses the analytical
potential to introduce methodical rational ways of life. Although theoretical
and formal types of rationality are also capable of indirect and direct
conscious mastery of reality, neither introduces con- sistent attitudes toward
life. Even though endowed with the capacity to do so, practical rational
patterns of action remain simply reactions to heterogeneous realities. Thus,
the practical rational way of life, char- acterized by a means-end rational
calculation of interests, lacks the me- thodical element called forth when
values, particularly those believed in as ethical standards, regulate action
"from within." Only substantive ra- tionality possesses the
analytical potential to master-or rationalize- reality comprehensively. It does
so by consciously and methodically or- ganizing action into patterns that are
consistent with explicit value con- stellation.
-Abukhater, A.
B. E. D. (2009). Rethinking planning theory and practice: a glimmer of light
for prospects
of integrated planning to combat complex urban realities. Theoretical and
Empirical Researches in Urban Management, (11), 64. Retrieved from:
http://www.um.ase.ro/No11/5.pdf
<script async src="https://pagead2.googlesyndication.com/pagead/js/adsbygoogle.js?client=ca-pub-4267074632853356"
crossorigin="anonymous"></script>
No comments:
Post a Comment